I was reading Nagarjuna’s Madhyamaka by Jan Westerhoff, when I came across the following sentence on page 27:
‘It is interesting to note that in the later dGe lugs commentarial tradition, three varieties of existential dependence are distinguished: causal dependence, when an object depends for its existence on its causes and conditions; mereological dependence, when an object depends on its parts; and conceptual dependence, postulating the dependence of an object on a basis of designation, a designating mind, and a term used to designate the object.’
Mereological dependence |
Mereological?
Now there’s a word I’d never come across before. So I looked it up in Wiki…
‘In philosophy and mathematical logic, mereology (from the Greek μέρος, root: μερε(σ)-, "part" and the suffix -logy "study, discussion, science") treats parts and the wholes they form…
…Standard university texts on logic and mathematics are silent about mereology, which has undoubtedly contributed to its obscurity.’ That probably explains why I had never heard of it before.
As Tom Etter puts it:
“Mereology? What on Earth is that?” you ask. Well you may ask, since you won't find the word in the American Heritage dictionary, nor even in the 8-volume Encyclopedia of Philosophy. However, if you look in the more enlightened Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy, you'll discover that mereology is “the mathematical theory of parts and wholes.” A very useful word, wouldn't you say? How have we managed all these years to get along without it?'
Googling around, I found an article by Greg Goode that explains mereological dependency as follows:
‘The way a thing depends on its pieces and parts. In Western philosophical terms, this might be referred to as mereological dependency. The pieces and parts of an object are sometimes called its "basis of designation." According to the emptiness teachings, we would see roots, a stalk, branches and leaves, and based on this, designate the object as a "tree." These various parts are the tree's basis of designation. Being a tree is dependent upon the basis of designation. The tree cannot be said to exist if its basis of designation did not exist.
For example, if you have a car in the parking lot over a long period of time, and vandals come and steal pieces here and there over several months, there will come a certain point at which there won't be enough parts for you to call it a car. This is how the car depends upon its pieces and parts, or its basis of designation. Even though this seems reasonable if we think about it like this, it's nevertheless easy to think that the true car exists in a way apart from the basis of designation, as though there were a "true car" that existed in an ideal realm of some sort. This sense that the car exists without depending on its basis of designation is the sense of the inherent existence of the car. This is more subtle than "Meeting"-style dependence.'
Top-down implies bottom-up
In Engaging Buddhism page 33, Jay Garfield points out that in Buddhist philosophy mereological dependency works both ways.
"As a consequence of the rejection of the ultimate existence of infinitesimal parts, the dependence relation between parts and wholes came to be recognized as a two-way street. Given that there is no ultimate decomposition of wholes into parts, the identification of any part as a part came to be seen as a matter of decompositional interest, just as the identification of a condition as an explanans is seen as dependent upon explanatory interests.
For something to exist as a part of a whole, on this view, is to be dependent on the whole in two respects. First, if the whole does not exist, the part does not exist as the kind of thing it is when it figures in the whole.
To take Wittgenstein's example in Philosophical Investigations, a brake lever is only a brake lever, and not simply a metal rod, in the context of a car in which it so functions (§6).
A biological organ, such as a heart, depends on an entire organism to develop, to function and to be an organ at all.
Second, decomposition can be accomplished in many ways. We might say that a memory chip is a part of a computer if we are decomposing it functionally, and that the parts of the chip are circuits, and so on. On the other hand, we might decompose the computer into adjacent 1 mm cubes, in which case the chip might turn out to be involved in several different parts, and not to be a part itself. If the whole in question is a solid volume, the cubes are parts; if it is a computer, the chip is a part, and 1 mm cubes are irrelevant. So, just as wholes depend on their parts, parts depend on their wholes."
Mere Mereology isn't enough
On further reflection I realised that I had in fact come across the Greek root ‘meros’ ('part') before - back in the dim and distant past of school organic chemistry lessons...
From Wiki: ‘In chemistry, isomers (from Greek ἰσομερής, isomerès; isos = "equal", méros = "part") are compounds with the same molecular formula but different structural formulas. Isomers do not necessarily share similar properties, unless they also have the same functional groups. There are many different classes of isomers, like stereoisomers, enantiomers, geometrical isomers, etc. There are two main forms of isomerism: structural isomerism and stereoisomerism (spatial isomerism).’
So, we can have objects composed of exactly the same parts - molecules made of identical numbers of identical atoms - but whose properties differ physically, chemically and biologically. Even subtle differences of orientation such as mirror-imaging of atoms within molecules can drastically change their biological activities.
Optical isomers |
Alternative terms to ‘Mereology’
This raises the question of whether the term ‘mereology’ is altogether adequate as a description of this second level of existential dependence. Some notion of structure and arrangement, in addition to a simple list of parts, is required. If you randomly throw together all the components in the designer’s bill of materials for a car you won’t get a working vehicle...
Geshe Kelsang Gyatso, in Joyful Path of Good Fortune pages 348 to 349, when discussing the three levels of existential dependence includes ‘parts’ to mean ‘aspects, divisions and directions’. Tom Etter in ‘Quantum Mechanics as a Branch of Mereology’ extends the scope of mereology beyond its standard definitions to include the ‘mereology of relations’ – in other words all those concepts handled by Relational Databases, for example entity/attributes and substructures.
New terminology needed?
So is there a more suitable single word in English than mereology to describe this second level of existential dependence?
The word would not only have to include the relations of parts to whole, and whole to parts, but also include the following relations:
- orientation
- composition
- connection
- arrangement
- configuration
- topology
- combination
- layout
- attributes
- properties
- structure and substructure
To anyone who works with with relational databases, especially as used for product specifications, the all-inclusive concept is familiar. It’s just that there isn’t a word for it in English. (Maybe the Sanskrit term rupa comes closer).
Anyone got any ideas?
- Sean Robsville
3 comments:
Thank you very much. I'm working on the same text with a student, and this exegesis of mereology will be very helpful. BTW, the spellchecker just underlined mereology.
There are not only three kind of dependencies. There are much more.
See: http://philpapers.org/rec/KOHPIE
Thomaso
http://ctkohl.googlepages.com
Most interesting; am exploring mereology as a tool for the construction of a new form of social networking, problem-solving, and consciousness-shifting frameworks and software. ¿Are you still engaged in this pursuit? Would love to connect...
Post a Comment